Nuclear Weapons: the Legal Status of Use, Threat and Possession

Introduction

In April 2010 the President of the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) declared: “the ICRC finds it difficult to envisage how any use of nuclear weapons could be compatible with the rules of international humanitarian law.”1“Bringing the era of nuclear weapons to an end”, statement by Jakob Kellenberger, 20 April 2010, Just over a month later, the 2010 NPT Review Conference “expresse[d] its deep concern at the catastrophic humanitarian consequences of any use of nuclear weapons and reaffirm[ed] the need for all States at all times to comply with applicable international law, including international humanitarian law.” It also “reaffirm[ed] the unequivocal undertaking of the nuclear-weapon States to accomplish the total elimination of their nuclear arsenals leading to nuclear disarmament, to which all States parties are committed under article VI.”2 2010 Review Conference of the Parties to the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons, Final Document, Volume 1, Part 1, p 19, Conclusions and recommendations for follow-on actions, I.A.v and ii. Doc NPT/CONF.2010/50 (Vol. I).

The links between possession, proliferation and use are self-evident. The probability of use increases as the number of nuclear-weapon States rises, and the probability of proliferation increases if the commitments of the Non-Proliferation Treaty are not honoured.

In these remarks on the legal status of the use, threatened use and possession of nuclear weapons, our focus will be upon United Kingdom practice. We begin with use because the legality of use determines the legality of threatened use and, in part, of possession.

Use

The use of nuclear weapons in any realistic military scenario would violate international law, chiefly because their blast, heat and especially their radiation effects could not be limited as required by international humanitarian law (IHL).3Cf the UK Government‘s submission to the ICJ: “In some cases, such as the use of a low-yield nuclear weapon against warships on the high seas or troops in sparsely populated areas, it is possible to envisage a nuclear attack which caused comparatively few civilian casualties.” As the ICJ observed in the Nuclear Weapons Case, their destructive power cannot be contained in either space or time.4 Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, ICJ Reports 1996, p 226, para 35.

In its advisory opinion, the World Court explained the “cardinal principles contained in the texts constituting the fabric of humanitarian law” as follows:

“The first is aimed at the protection of the civilian population and civilian objects and establishes the distinction between combatants and non-combatants; States must never make civilians the object of attack and must consequently never use weapons that are incapable of distinguishing between civilian [objects] and military targets. According to the second principle, it is prohibited to cause unnecessary suffering to combatants: it is accordingly prohibited to use weapons causing them such harm or uselessly aggravating their suffering. In application of that second principle, States do not have unlimited freedom of choice of means in the weapons they use.”5Ibid, para 78.

In light of those fundamental rules of IHL, which it described as “intransgressible principles of international customary law,”6Ibid, para 79 the Court clearly doubted whether nuclear weapons could ever be used lawfully. In view of “the unique characteristics of nuclear weapons, and in particular their destructive capacity, their capacity to cause untold human suffering and their ability to cause damage to generations to come,” it observed that the use of such weapons “seems scarcely reconcilable” with respect for the law of armed conflict, “at the heart of which is the overriding consideration of humanity.”7 Ibid, paras 36, 79 and 95.

Nevertheless, the ICJ considered that it did not have “sufficient elements of fact or law to enable it to conclude with certainty that the use of nuclear weapons would necessarily be at variance with [IHL] in any circumstance.”8Ibid, para 95. Accordingly, whilst it held9 By seven votes to seven, by the President‘s casting vote. that “the threat or use of nuclear weapons would generally be contrary to the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict, and in particular the principles and rules of humanitarian law,” it could not “conclude definitively whether the threat or use of nuclear weapons would be lawful or unlawful in an extreme circumstance of selfdefence, in which the very survival of a State would be at stake.” 10Nuclear Weapons Case, para 105, point 2E of the dispositif.

As President Bedjaoui emphasised in his Declaration, however, the Court was not thereby recognising an in extremis exception to the general prohibition of threat or use: “I cannot sufficiently emphasize that the Court’s inability to go beyond this statement of the situation can in no way be interpreted to mean that it is leaving the door ajar to recognition of the legality of the threat or use of nuclear weapons.” 11 ICJ Reports 1996, p 270, para 11.

In contrast, the UK Government‘s response has been that the advisory opinion does not: “require a change in the United Kingdom’s entirely defensive deterrence policy. We would only ever consider the use of nuclear weapons in the extreme circumstance of self-defence which includes the defence of our NATO allies.”12 Hansard, House of Lords Debates, 26 January 1998, Col 7. See also UK Ministry of Defence, The Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict, Oxford University Press, 2004, para 6.17.1.

But this wrongly assumes that the ICJ acknowledged an in extremis exception to the prohibition of threat or use, whereas the Court did not say that nuclear weapons may be used in extremis.

The UK Government would probably contend that restrictions on the actions of States cannot be presumed.13 The Lotus Case, PCIJ, Series A, No 10, p 18. In the advisory opinion proceedings it argued that “it is … axiomatic that, in the absence of a prohibitive rule applicable to a particular State, the conduct of the State in question must be permissible.”14United Kingdom, Written Submission on the Opinion requested by the General Assembly, p 21. However, there is no room for such an argument here. It is not ‘good faith’ interpretation of the advisory opinion, the text and tenor of which clearly indicate the Court‘s strong inclination towards illegality in all circumstances.15 At para 104 of its opinion in the Nuclear Weapons Case, the ICJ emphasised that its reply to the General Assembly‘s question “rests on the totality of the legal grounds set forth by the Court, each of which has to be read in the light of the others.” Furthermore, any insistence on a specific legal prohibition, which “can only be attributable to an extreme form of positivism,”16Nuclear Weapons Case, dissenting opinion of Judge Koroma, p 14. ignores the fact that States co-exist within a circumscribing boundary of norms or principles. 17 Cf Judge Weeramantry‘s dissenting opinion in the Lockerbie Case (Provisional Measures), ICJ Reports, 1992, pp 3, 51. These include elementary considerations of humanity18 Corfu Channel Case, ICJ Reports 1949, pp 4, 22. The ICJ listed “elementary considerations of humanity, even more exacting in peace than in war” among “certain general and well-recognized principles” on which Albania‘s obligations to notify the existence of a minefield in its territorial waters and warn approaching British warships of the imminent dangers were based. and the fundamental rules of IHL which bind all States whether or not they are parties to the conventions that contain them and which are themselves infused with the overriding consideration of humanity. 19 Nuclear Weapons Case, paras 79 and 95 Reference may also be made to the continuing constraints of the Martens Clause, named after the Russian delegate at the Hague Peace Conference 1899. As the ICJ observed, a modern version of that clause provides:

“In cases not covered by this Protocol or by other international agreements, civilians and combatants remain under the protection and authority of the principles of international law derived from established custom, from the principles of humanity and from the dictates of public conscience.”20 Ibid, para 78, referring to Protocol I of 1977 Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (hereafter Additional Protocol I). At para 87 the Court held that the Martens Clause‘s “continuing existence and applicability is not to be doubted.”

Similar objections apply to this comment on the advisory opinion by a former Deputy Legal Adviser of the Foreign and Commonwealth Office: “The Court does not appear to have considered the, admittedly paradoxical, possibility that in certain exceptional situations the threat or even use of nuclear weapons might be done altruistically to support demands by it or the United Nations for the observance of fundamental human rights, such as the prohibitions on genocide or, indeed, the use of other weapons of mass destruction against a third State.”21 A Aust, Handbook of International Law, Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition, 2010, pp 239-240.

It would not be lawful for a State to use nuclear weapons to support such demands by the UN Security Council or the ICJ, which is the UN‘s principal judicial organ.22Article 92 of the UN Charter and Article 1 of the Statute of the ICJ, which forms an integral part of the Charter. A weapon which cannot be used consistently with the fundamental rules of IHL and the principles of humanity does not become lawful because it is being used for a legitimate purpose under the Charter. 23Cf para 39 of the Nuclear Weapons Case. Any use of nuclear weapons would be inconsistent with the purposes and principles of the UN24 Article 24(2) of the Charter provides that “the Security Council shall act in accordance with the Purposes and Principles of the United Nations.” Article 1(1) refers to the peaceful settlement of disputes “in conformity with the principles of justice and international law” and Article 1(3) emphasises the UN‘s important role in promoting and encouraging respect for human rights. and subvert the rule of law. Furthermore, attacks on civilians by way of reprisal can never be justified.25 See e.g. Article 51(6) of Additional Protocol I; and ICTY, Trial Chamber, 14 January 2000, Case No IT-95-16, Prosecutor v Kupreskić, Part V, paras 520-533. Under Article 60(5) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969, moreover, the doctrine of material breach does not apply to “provisions relating to the protection of the human person contained in treaties of a humanitarian character, in particular to provisions prohibiting any form of reprisals against persons protected by such treaties.”

The UK Government argues that nuclear weapons fall to be dealt with by the same general principles as apply to conventional weapons and that the legality of their use in a particular case would depend on all the circumstances. 26UK Ministry of Defence, op cit, 6.17. On ratifying Additional Protocol I,27 See note 21. moreover, the Government stated:

“It continues to be the understanding of the United Kingdom that the rules introduced by the Protocol apply exclusively to conventional weapons without prejudice to any other rules of international law applicable to other types of weapons. In particular, the rules so introduced do not have any effect on and do not regulate or prohibit the use of nuclear weapons.”28See The Geneva Conventions Act (First Protocol) Order 1998 (SI 1998 No 1754) and The International Criminal Court Act 2001 (Reservations and Declarations) Order 2001 (SI 2001 No 2559).

But that statement, which is arguably a reservation,29 Article 2(1)(d) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969 defines a reservation as “a unilateral statement, however phrased or named, made by a State, when signing, ratifying…or acceding to a treaty whereby it purports to exclude or to modify the legal effect of certain provisions of the treaty in their application to that State.” Under Article 19(c) of the Convention, a reservation which is incompatible with the object and purpose of the treaty is impermissible applies only to “the rules introduced by the Protocol,” such as the rule requiring protection of the environment.30 Articles 35(3) and 55 of Additional Protocol I, in respect of which the UK statement is arguably an impermissible reservation. It does not affect those provisions which were declaratory of customary international law, such as the prohibition against causing unnecessary suffering to combatants and the requirement to distinguish between civilian objects and military objectives. The ICJ emphasised that “all States are bound by those rules in Additional Protocol I which, when adopted, were merely the expression of the pre-existing customary law.” 31 Nuclear Weapons Case, para 84. The UK has also reserved the right to take measures otherwise prohibited by Articles 51 and 55 of Additional Protocol I (concerning protection of the civilian population) “to the extent that it considers such measures necessary for the purpose of compelling the adverse party to cease committing violations under those Articles.” Some argue that this would entitle the UK to use nuclear weapons as a form of legitimate reprisal against a State which used them against it. As explained above, however, attacks on civilians by way of reprisal can never be justified, so to that extent, at least, the reservation is impermissible.

Threat

In the Nuclear Weapons Case, the ICJ observed that there is a symbiotic relationship between ‗use‘ and ‗threat‘: “Whether a signalled intention to use force if certain events occur is or is not a “threat” within Article 2, paragraph 4, of the Charter depends upon various factors. If the envisaged use of force is itself unlawful, the stated readiness to use it would be a threat prohibited under Article 2, paragraph 4…. The notions of “threat” and “use” of force under Article 2, paragraph 4, of the Charter stand together in the sense that if the use of force itself in a given case is illegal – for whatever reason – the threat to use such force will likewise be illegal…”32 Ibid, para 47.

In March 2001 a Scottish appeal court rejected the contention that the general deployment of Trident pursuant to a policy of deterrence constituted a ‘threat’ to use it.33Lord Advocate‘s Reference (No 1 of 2000), 2001 SCCR 296, para 98.  Its assessment echoed that of a former Lord Advocate, Lord Murray, an opponent of Trident, who in a 1998 lecture said: “to possess nuclear submarines supplied with weapons which it is illegal to use is not of itself unlawful; nor would it be unlawful for them to be put to sea in a general state of operational readiness. But to deploy them with definite targets in face of hostile confrontation could constitute a threat in law.”34 Lord Murray, “Can Trident missiles be lawfully used in light of the decision of the International Court of Justice in the Nuclear Weapons Case?”, May 1998.

It is true that in 2005 the then Secretary of State for Defence, John Reid, told Parliament: “All the UK’s Trident missiles have been de-targeted since 1994, and the submarine on deterrent patrol is normally at several days’ notice to fire. The missiles can be targeted in sufficient time to meet any foreseeable requirement.”35 Hansard, House of Commons, 27 October 2005, Col 522W.

This was consistent with the 1998 Strategic Defence Review‘s statement that the notice to fire had been relaxed from “a few minutes” to “days.”36Strategic Defence Review, July 1998, Supporting Essay Five: “Deterrence, Arms Control, and Proliferation,” para 12: However, bearing in mind that this is unverifiable37 Commander Robert Green, Security Without Nuclear Deterrence, Astron Media and The Disarmament & Security Centre, 2010, p 226. and that in any event the system could be brought rapidly to readiness at a time of crisis,38 House of Commons Library, Research Paper 06/53, ―The Future of the British Nuclear Deterrent,‖ 3 November 2006, p 22: http://www.isn.ethz.ch/isn/DigitalLibrary/Publications/Detail/?id=44160&lng=en. the Scottish court‘s assessment is at odds with the ICJ‘s analysis. The deployment of Trident pursuant to the UK Government‘s policy of continuous at sea deterrence39 i.e. at least one nuclear-armed submarine is on patrol at any time. signals an intention to use force if certain events occur, and that is surely a ‘threat‘ within Article 2 if for any reason the envisaged use of force would be unlawful. According to the ICJ,

“Possession of nuclear weapons may indeed justify an inference of preparedness to use them. In order to be effective, the policy of deterrence … necessitates that the intention to use nuclear weapons be credible. Whether this is a “threat” contrary to Article 2, paragraph 4, depends upon whether the particular use of force envisaged would be directed against the territorial integrity or political independence of a State, or against the Purposes of the United Nations or whether, in the event that it were intended as a means of defence, it would necessarily violate the principles of necessity and proportionality. In any of these circumstances the use of force, and the threat to use it, would be unlawful under the law of the Charter.”40 Ibid, para 48. Emphasis added.

Although the ICJ declined to pronounce upon the practice known as ‘the policy of deterrence’ as such,41 Ibid, para 67. it seems to have accepted that the deployment of nuclear weapons pursuant to an effective policy of deterrence is a ‘threat’ to use them. Instead, it was concerned with legality. In that regard, the Court made it clear that the UN Charter is not the only reference point: “The proportionality principle may thus not in itself exclude the use of nuclear weapons in self-defence in all circumstances. 42 In terms of the proportionality principle, the ICJ observed that the very nature of all nuclear weapons and the profound risks associated with them, including environmental considerations, would have to be borne in mind But at the same time, a use of force that is proportionate under the law of selfdefence, must, in order to be lawful, also meet the requirements of the law applicable in armed conflict which comprise in particular the principles and rules of humanitarian law.”43 Nuclear Weapons Case, para 42. See also para 105, point 2D: “A threat or use of nuclear weapons should also be compatible with the requirements of the international law applicable in armed conflict, particularly those of the principles and rules of international humanitarian law…”

Since the use of nuclear weapons would violate IHL, especially because their destructive power cannot be contained in either space or time,44Ibid, para 35. their threatened use is likewise illegal. Under Article 51(2) of Additional Protocol I, moreover, “[a]cts or threats of violence the primary purpose of which is to spread terror among the civilian population are prohibited.”45Emphasis added.

Possession

In view of the ICJ‘s description of the fundamental rules of IHL as “intransgressible principles of international customary law,” and even though it decided that there was no need to pronounce on the rules‘ legal character,46Ibid, para 83. The Court considered that the General Assembly‘s request did not raise this question. it is appropriate to regard them as jus cogens: peremptory norms of general international law from which no derogation is permitted.47 See Article 53 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969 and J Crawford, The International Law Commission’s Articles on State Responsibility, Cambridge University Press, 2002, p 246. They are compelling law, norms that enjoy “a higher rank in the international hierarchy than treaty law and even “ordinary” customary rules.” 48Prosecutor v Furundzija, ICTY, Case No IT-95-17/1-T, para 153. The ICTY continued: “The most conspicuous consequence of this higher rank is that the principle at issue cannot be derogated from by States through international treaties or local or special or even general customary rules not endowed with the same normative force.” (1999) 38 ILM 317. States must bring their practice into conformity with such rules.

The superior status of the fundamental rules of IHL in the hierarchy of international legal norms was confirmed in the Wall Case where the ICJ held that they “incorporate obligations which are essentially of an erga omnes character.”49Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory, Advisory Opinion, 9 July 1994, para 157. In para 19 of her separate opinion, Judge Higgins emphasised that “the protection of civilians remains an intransgressible obligation of humanitarian law.” This means that those obligations are the concern of all States and that all States have a legal interest in the protection of the rights involved.50Ibid, para 155 with a reference to the Barcelona Traction Case, ICJ Reports 1970, p 32, para 33.

Such norms generate strong interpretative principles51 Crawford, op cit, p 187. which prevent the Nuclear NonProliferation Treaty (NPT) from being construed as legalising the possession of nuclear weapons. Yet the UK Government claims that the NPT allows the United Kingdom to have nuclear weapons since the treaty recognises it as “a nuclear-weapon State.”52 See e.g. Hansard, House of Commons, 1 March 2005, Col 805. It is true that Article IX.3 of the NPT defines such a State as one which has manufactured and exploded a nuclear weapon or other nuclear explosive device prior to 1 January 1967.” But that is purely a factual definition and strictly for the purposes of the NPT only. 53 The relevant sentence of Article IX.3 begins: “For the purposes of this Treaty,…” It does not legalise the possession of nuclear weapons. To construe the NPT as if it did is not ‘good faith’ interpretation or performance as required by the law of treaties, 54See Articles 26 and 31(1) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969. especially in view of the jus cogens / erga omnes character of the fundamental rules of IHL and the ICJ‘s interpretation of Article VI of the NPT.55Article VI provides: “Each of the Parties to the Treaty undertakes to pursue negotiations in good faith on effective measures relating to cessation of the nuclear arms race at an early date and to nuclear disarmament, and on a Treaty on general and complete disarmament under strict and effective international control.” The Court concluded its advisory opinion in the Nuclear Weapons Case by unanimously holding: “There exists an obligation to pursue in good faith and bring to a conclusion negotiations leading to nuclear disarmament in all aspects under strict and effective international control.”56 Nuclear Weapons Case, para 105, point 2F of the dispositif.

The Court also declared that fulfilling the obligation expressed in Article VI “remains without any doubt an objective of vital importance to the whole of the international community today.”57Ibid, para 103. This is tantamount to declaring that the twofold obligation to negotiate in good faith and conclude a nuclear disarmament treaty is an obligation erga omnes, complementing and reinforcing the jus cogens / erga omnes nature of the fundamental rules of IHL.58 Since it enshrines an obligation erga omnes, Article VI might also have jus cogens status. See Crawford, op cit, p 244: “Whether or not peremptory norms of general international law and obligations to the international community as a whole are aspects of a single basic idea, there is at the very least substantial overlap between them…” The logical legal consequence of this combination of erga omnes obligations and fundamental rules is that the use, the threatened use and arguably even the possession of nuclear weapons are illegal. Such weapons cannot lawfully be employed or deployed and there is a legal obligation to negotiate in good faith for, and ensure, their elimination.59The link between illegality of use and illegality of possession is illustrated by the case of three Danish soldiers who in 2009 were sent home from Afghanistan and accused of possessing illegal ammunition. They were charged with having dum-dum bullets in their pistols. There was no indication that any of the soldiers had ever fired the bullets. See www.globalresearch.ca/PrintArticle.php?articleId=15490. Hague Declaration 3 of 1899 concerning Expanding Bullets, which reflects customary international law, prohibits the use of dum-dum bullets because they cause unnecessary suffering

Conclusion

Some people say that in trying to deal with such matters we are beyond the limits of law, but we are not. Law must play a decisive role as the embodiment of normative values. The rule of law is a fundamental principle of civilised society and respect for the rule of law is an essential prerequisite of international order. This is how the late Lord Bingham, one of the UK‘s greatest jurists, put it: “The rule of law requires compliance by the State with its obligations in international law as in national law.”60 T Bingham, The Rule of Law, Allen Lane, 2010, p 110. In a lecture on the same theme he added: “I do not think this proposition is contentious.”61 The Sixth Sir David Williams Lecture, “The Rule of Law”, University of Cambridge, 16 November 2006.

Either we have the rule of law or we do not. In reaching its conclusion about the illegality of nuclear weapons in the Nuclear Weapons Case, the ICJ felt that it could not ignore the “policy of deterrence” to which an appreciable section of the international community had adhered for many years.62 Nuclear Weapons Case, paras 95-96 As Judge Shi declared, however, the policy of nuclear deterrence should be an object of regulation by law, not vice versa.63ICJ Reports 1996, p 277. International law is not simply whatever those with ‘the say’ (in practice, the nuclear-weapon States) say it is.

 

ABOUT THE AUTHOR

  • PROF. NICHOLAS GRIEF is a professor in Kent Law School and practices at the Bar from Doughty Street Chambers, London where he is a member of the International Law Group. He has appeared in several cases concerning the legality of Trident, sometimes as an expert witness. In 2007 he gave evidence to the House of Commons Defence Committee on the legal implications of the White Paper on the future of the UK’s strategic nuclear deterrent. He also lectures on EU law at the National School of Government and is a visiting member of the Center of Theological Inquiry, Princeton. This is a revised version of a paper given at the conference on “Humanitarian Law, Human Security: The Emerging Paradigm for Non-Use and Elimination of Nuclear Weapons” in Vancouver, February 10-11, 2011

References   [ + ]

1. “Bringing the era of nuclear weapons to an end”, statement by Jakob Kellenberger, 20 April 2010,
2. 2010 Review Conference of the Parties to the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons, Final Document, Volume 1, Part 1, p 19, Conclusions and recommendations for follow-on actions, I.A.v and ii. Doc NPT/CONF.2010/50 (Vol. I).
3. Cf the UK Government‘s submission to the ICJ: “In some cases, such as the use of a low-yield nuclear weapon against warships on the high seas or troops in sparsely populated areas, it is possible to envisage a nuclear attack which caused comparatively few civilian casualties.”
4. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, ICJ Reports 1996, p 226, para 35.
5. Ibid, para 78.
6. Ibid, para 79
7. Ibid, paras 36, 79 and 95.
8. Ibid, para 95.
9. By seven votes to seven, by the President‘s casting vote.
10. Nuclear Weapons Case, para 105, point 2E of the dispositif.
11. ICJ Reports 1996, p 270, para 11.
12. Hansard, House of Lords Debates, 26 January 1998, Col 7. See also UK Ministry of Defence, The Manual of the Law of Armed Conflict, Oxford University Press, 2004, para 6.17.1.
13. The Lotus Case, PCIJ, Series A, No 10, p 18.
14. United Kingdom, Written Submission on the Opinion requested by the General Assembly, p 21.
15. At para 104 of its opinion in the Nuclear Weapons Case, the ICJ emphasised that its reply to the General Assembly‘s question “rests on the totality of the legal grounds set forth by the Court, each of which has to be read in the light of the others.”
16. Nuclear Weapons Case, dissenting opinion of Judge Koroma, p 14.
17. Cf Judge Weeramantry‘s dissenting opinion in the Lockerbie Case (Provisional Measures), ICJ Reports, 1992, pp 3, 51.
18. Corfu Channel Case, ICJ Reports 1949, pp 4, 22. The ICJ listed “elementary considerations of humanity, even more exacting in peace than in war” among “certain general and well-recognized principles” on which Albania‘s obligations to notify the existence of a minefield in its territorial waters and warn approaching British warships of the imminent dangers were based.
19. Nuclear Weapons Case, paras 79 and 95
20. Ibid, para 78, referring to Protocol I of 1977 Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (hereafter Additional Protocol I). At para 87 the Court held that the Martens Clause‘s “continuing existence and applicability is not to be doubted.”
21. A Aust, Handbook of International Law, Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition, 2010, pp 239-240.
22. Article 92 of the UN Charter and Article 1 of the Statute of the ICJ, which forms an integral part of the Charter.
23. Cf para 39 of the Nuclear Weapons Case.
24. Article 24(2) of the Charter provides that “the Security Council shall act in accordance with the Purposes and Principles of the United Nations.” Article 1(1) refers to the peaceful settlement of disputes “in conformity with the principles of justice and international law” and Article 1(3) emphasises the UN‘s important role in promoting and encouraging respect for human rights.
25. See e.g. Article 51(6) of Additional Protocol I; and ICTY, Trial Chamber, 14 January 2000, Case No IT-95-16, Prosecutor v Kupreskić, Part V, paras 520-533. Under Article 60(5) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969, moreover, the doctrine of material breach does not apply to “provisions relating to the protection of the human person contained in treaties of a humanitarian character, in particular to provisions prohibiting any form of reprisals against persons protected by such treaties.”
26. UK Ministry of Defence, op cit, 6.17.
27. See note 21.
28. See The Geneva Conventions Act (First Protocol) Order 1998 (SI 1998 No 1754) and The International Criminal Court Act 2001 (Reservations and Declarations) Order 2001 (SI 2001 No 2559).
29. Article 2(1)(d) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969 defines a reservation as “a unilateral statement, however phrased or named, made by a State, when signing, ratifying…or acceding to a treaty whereby it purports to exclude or to modify the legal effect of certain provisions of the treaty in their application to that State.” Under Article 19(c) of the Convention, a reservation which is incompatible with the object and purpose of the treaty is impermissible
30. Articles 35(3) and 55 of Additional Protocol I, in respect of which the UK statement is arguably an impermissible reservation.
31. Nuclear Weapons Case, para 84. The UK has also reserved the right to take measures otherwise prohibited by Articles 51 and 55 of Additional Protocol I (concerning protection of the civilian population) “to the extent that it considers such measures necessary for the purpose of compelling the adverse party to cease committing violations under those Articles.” Some argue that this would entitle the UK to use nuclear weapons as a form of legitimate reprisal against a State which used them against it. As explained above, however, attacks on civilians by way of reprisal can never be justified, so to that extent, at least, the reservation is impermissible.
32. Ibid, para 47.
33. Lord Advocate‘s Reference (No 1 of 2000), 2001 SCCR 296, para 98.
34. Lord Murray, “Can Trident missiles be lawfully used in light of the decision of the International Court of Justice in the Nuclear Weapons Case?”, May 1998.
35. Hansard, House of Commons, 27 October 2005, Col 522W.
36. Strategic Defence Review, July 1998, Supporting Essay Five: “Deterrence, Arms Control, and Proliferation,” para 12:
37. Commander Robert Green, Security Without Nuclear Deterrence, Astron Media and The Disarmament & Security Centre, 2010, p 226.
38. House of Commons Library, Research Paper 06/53, ―The Future of the British Nuclear Deterrent,‖ 3 November 2006, p 22: http://www.isn.ethz.ch/isn/DigitalLibrary/Publications/Detail/?id=44160&lng=en.
39. i.e. at least one nuclear-armed submarine is on patrol at any time.
40. Ibid, para 48. Emphasis added.
41. Ibid, para 67.
42. In terms of the proportionality principle, the ICJ observed that the very nature of all nuclear weapons and the profound risks associated with them, including environmental considerations, would have to be borne in mind
43. Nuclear Weapons Case, para 42. See also para 105, point 2D: “A threat or use of nuclear weapons should also be compatible with the requirements of the international law applicable in armed conflict, particularly those of the principles and rules of international humanitarian law…”
44. Ibid, para 35.
45. Emphasis added.
46. Ibid, para 83. The Court considered that the General Assembly‘s request did not raise this question.
47. See Article 53 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969 and J Crawford, The International Law Commission’s Articles on State Responsibility, Cambridge University Press, 2002, p 246.
48. Prosecutor v Furundzija, ICTY, Case No IT-95-17/1-T, para 153. The ICTY continued: “The most conspicuous consequence of this higher rank is that the principle at issue cannot be derogated from by States through international treaties or local or special or even general customary rules not endowed with the same normative force.” (1999) 38 ILM 317.
49. Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory, Advisory Opinion, 9 July 1994, para 157. In para 19 of her separate opinion, Judge Higgins emphasised that “the protection of civilians remains an intransgressible obligation of humanitarian law.”
50. Ibid, para 155 with a reference to the Barcelona Traction Case, ICJ Reports 1970, p 32, para 33.
51. Crawford, op cit, p 187.
52. See e.g. Hansard, House of Commons, 1 March 2005, Col 805.
53. The relevant sentence of Article IX.3 begins: “For the purposes of this Treaty,…”
54. See Articles 26 and 31(1) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969.
55. Article VI provides: “Each of the Parties to the Treaty undertakes to pursue negotiations in good faith on effective measures relating to cessation of the nuclear arms race at an early date and to nuclear disarmament, and on a Treaty on general and complete disarmament under strict and effective international control.”
56. Nuclear Weapons Case, para 105, point 2F of the dispositif.
57. Ibid, para 103.
58. Since it enshrines an obligation erga omnes, Article VI might also have jus cogens status. See Crawford, op cit, p 244: “Whether or not peremptory norms of general international law and obligations to the international community as a whole are aspects of a single basic idea, there is at the very least substantial overlap between them…”
59. The link between illegality of use and illegality of possession is illustrated by the case of three Danish soldiers who in 2009 were sent home from Afghanistan and accused of possessing illegal ammunition. They were charged with having dum-dum bullets in their pistols. There was no indication that any of the soldiers had ever fired the bullets. See www.globalresearch.ca/PrintArticle.php?articleId=15490. Hague Declaration 3 of 1899 concerning Expanding Bullets, which reflects customary international law, prohibits the use of dum-dum bullets because they cause unnecessary suffering
60. T Bingham, The Rule of Law, Allen Lane, 2010, p 110.
61. The Sixth Sir David Williams Lecture, “The Rule of Law”, University of Cambridge, 16 November 2006.
62. Nuclear Weapons Case, paras 95-96
63. ICJ Reports 1996, p 277.
Nicholas Grief

About Nicholas Grief

PROF. NICHOLAS GRIEF is a professor in Kent Law School and practices at the Bar from Doughty Street Chambers, London where he is a member of the International Law Group. He has appeared in several cases concerning the legality of Trident, sometimes as an expert witness. In 2007 he gave evidence to the House of Commons Defence Committee on the legal implications of the White Paper on the future of the UK’s strategic nuclear deterrent. He also lectures on EU law at the National School of Government and is a visiting member of the Center of Theological Inquiry, Princeton.

  •